Guest guest Posted August 29, 2007 Report Share Posted August 29, 2007 I'm sorry this is so long, but knew many were not members with passwords. I'll let you decided how you feel about this article. From American Journal of Transplantation In Defense of Transplantation: A Reply to Scheper- Posted 08/22/2007 B. E. Hippen; J. S. Content We read with disappointment the essay by Scheper- in which she compares living organ donation to 'sacrificial violence'. Tempting as it is to dismiss this kind of criticism as a simple provocation, Scheper- is the founder of Organs Watch, an organization publicly represented as exposing the egregious moral abuses of international organ trafficking. We believe such a solemn responsibility imposes additional obligations on both Scheper- and on her critics, since extravagant, misleading criticism can damage good causes and bad causes alike. Drawing on Scheper-'s past writings and current essay, we wish to place in context and then criticize her understanding of donation as 'sacrificial violence', her denial of any meaningful moral distinction between 'family bonds' and 'family bondage', her mischaracterization of the achievements of presumed consent policies in Europe, her parochial understanding of futility, and her pernicious characterizations of transplant professionals and of the endeavor of transplantation as a whole. After identifying and considering Scheper-'s criticisms we judge worthy of careful consideration, we conclude with general comments on the standards by which criticism of the practices of transplantation ought to be evaluated. In previous essays, Scheper- has characterized transplantation as 'neocannibalism', the legacy of which has been to spread a myth of immortality to vulnerable potential recipients: '...the transformation of a person into a " life " that must be prolonged or saved at any cost [which] has made life into the ultimate commodity fetish'. Indeed, until her essay in the American Journal of Transplantation, she had argued that the waiting list for organs was itself a myth, invented by transplant professionals solely for their personal and professional advancement: 'The specter of long transplant waiting lists?often only virtual lists with little material basis in reality?has motivated physicians, hospital administrators and various intermediaries to employ questionable tactics for procuring organs?. But this scarcity, created by the technicians of transplant surgery, represents an artificial need, one that can never be satisfied, for underlying it is the unprecedented possibility of extending life indefinitely with the organs of others'. This context is crucial to understanding Scheper-'s argument that all living donor?recipient relationships involve 'sacrificial violence', in which 'family bonds' are synonymous with 'family bondage'. Since for Scheper-, the 'need' for a transplant and the attendant illusion of shortage is a collective delusion eagerly supported by avaricious transplant professionals, it follows that their use of terms such as 'altruism' and 'family bonds' as alternative descriptors of the donor?recipient relationship is mere propaganda. Perhaps, Scheper-'s arguments in her AJT essay, which now exhort deceased donation, can be understood as an exercise in realpolitik: Transplantation may be based on a terrible lie, but better to focus one's efforts to turn its voracious appetite for organs from the dead instead of from the living. It is immaterial to Scheper- that her view is utterly at odds with conventional understandings of transplantation and donor?recipient relationships. As with any unfalsifiable conspiracy theory, the widespread rejection of her thesis among transplant professionals and medical ethicists who write on transplantation ethics only serves to prove how entrenched this delusion has become. A conspicuous feature of Scheper-'s criticisms is an indifference to countervailing arguments and evidence. For example, she has elsewhere argued that the lower rate of consent for deceased donation among Black and Hispanic families is best explained as '...a political act of considered resistance' against what she believes they see as the oppressive hegemony of transplant professionals. This is incompatible with the empirical evidence that has been collected on the issue, which shows that the most important variable predicting a lack of consent for donation from Black and Hispanic families is a lack of foreknowledge regarding the decedent's wishes[5,6] and misconceptions regarding the financial burdens of consenting to deceased donation and the concept of brain-death. Though she denies any meaningful moral difference between family bonds and 'family bondage'given that '...Families are often violent and predatory, as inclined to abuse and exploit as to protect and nurture their members' Scheper- offers no reason to accept this bleak view of human relationships. Moreover, it is simply unjustified to hold that the inherent moral asymmetry involved in giving the 'gift of life' is only (or even often) imbued with psychological indenture and resentment. Instead, an approach more receptive to the raw complexity and ambiguity of the moral lives of thoughtful human beings paints a picture of relationships slightly more diverse and textured than one of master and slave.[8] In fact, the anthropologist and social scientist who coined the term 'Tyranny of the Gift', emphasized and elucidated this diversity,, and more than fifty studies of psychosocial outcomes of living donors demonstrated either no change or a positive improvement in the psychological health of the vast majority of them. Scheper-'s indifference to, or unfamiliarity with, evidence concerning the issues she addresses is exemplified in her allusion to the alleged success of presumed consent policies in European countries. Her brief mention offers no reference to the manifest ethical concerns regarding presumed consent (reviewed in, overlooks the fact that such policies are not enforced in countries with the most robust rates of procurement,and at any rate are not causally related to improved organ procurement rates compared to countries without such policies. So, we turn with skepticism to Scheper-'s call for the 'restoration' of a 'social ethic' to transplantation, with the unfortunate implication that such an ethic was somehow lost. Acknowledging that deceased donor organs alone cannot attenuate the burgeoning need for organs, Scheper- admonishes the profession as '...unwilling...to examine the waiting list to see if futile cases cannot, in good faith, be removed and to establish age limits that would decrease the list by several thousand', She acknowledges that such a draconian, arbitrary measure would not be 'palatable', and that such patients would likely pursue transplantation through illicit means, including international organ trafficking, a point not lost on others opposed to trafficking. Given the salutary outcomes she herself cites for elderly recipients after transplantation compared to dialysis, it seems that when Scheper- characterizes this practice as 'futile' she must mean not that it is futile for the organ recipients themselves, but, rather, that it is futile with respect to providing organs for persons who are assumed to no longer be able to meaningfully contribute to society. She justifies this by an appeal to a 'cultural norm in American society' in which '...it is not generally expected that children be unstintingly devoted to their parents',. Not only does this norm overstate the act of being a living donor as 'unstinting devotion', but it is one which is also apparently overlooked by the estimated 44 million family caregivers in the United States, who do not find their unstinting devotion either unusual or morally troubling. Curiously, Scheper- fails to see that her view is simply a species of arguments from social worth, which dominated the early debates regarding the allocation of dialysis, the 'unpalatable' moral consequences of which resulted in vast reforms to eliminate such considerations from the allocation of life-saving therapy. As a practical matter, even if excluding candidates by age could withstand moral and legal scrutiny, and even if the subsequent, predictable increase in underground organ trafficking could somehow be attenuated, we and Scheper- should be concerned with likely effects that this measure would have on living donation. Without other means of pursuing transplantation, elderly recipients would likely rely on living donors even more than they currently do. And, as much as she might wish otherwise, transplant physicians who do not share Scheper-'s understanding of what is, and what is not, 'futile' treatment are unlikely to refuse medically qualified elderly recipients a transplant from a willing living donor. Though we reject Scheper-'s premises, we are obliged to salvage and highlight issues that she correctly identifies as worthy of moral attention. The gender imbalance among living donors noted by Scheper- is real, may in some circumstances be a product of power asymmetries in certain family relationships and is worthy of further scrutiny. The flourishing of international organ trafficking has generated demonstrable physical and psychological damage to vendors and recipients, and is an indelible moral stain on reputable transplantation. The growth in the number of elderly transplant candidates, a phenomenon which will only increase with the success, not the failure, of preventive medicine, is but the latest example of technical innovation resulting in the exchange of one set of problems (survival) for others (scarce resource allocation). The projected increase in the number of prevalent dialysis patients, and therefore the number of potential transplant recipients in the next 5 and 10 years, concomitant with the comparatively stagnant growth in the number of deceased donor organs, will only increase the pressure on traditional living donors to quell the desperation bred of a wholly inadequate public policy. These are the circumstances which threaten to render particularly vulnerable living donors more so. These are problems that urgently warrant our moral attention, which is why it is crucial, indeed, morally obligatory, that the challenges they pose are accurately explained and scrutinized. To this end, commentators on and chroniclers of transplantation have never shied from criticism. The standard by which criticism is judged is not whether the field of transplantation is helped or hindered, but rather whether such criticisms can be supported and substantiated by sound arguments and attention to the available evidence. Such a standard does not imply that such criticism must merely serve as handmaiden to the advancement of transplantation. ReneƩ Fox and Judith Swazey, after producing two decades' worth of exemplary critical scholarship in the field, publicly withdrew from their research, after concluding that public expenditures on organ transplantation could not be justified in a society which fails to provide universal access to health care. The critical efforts of anthropologists, sociologists, philosophers, economists and lawyers have morally improved the practice of transplantation, and its workings continue to be subjected to warranted scrutiny. It is also true that transplantation is predicated on a public trust informed and enhanced by criticism, but not entirely impervious to vandalism. While Scheper-'s concern with protecting vulnerable people is admirable, her flawed, unfortunate essay is a reminder to those struggling to advance a morally informed practice of transplantation that maintaining the public trust obliges us to distinguish between the two. Quote Link to comment Share on other sites More sharing options...
Guest guest Posted August 29, 2007 Report Share Posted August 29, 2007 Barb, I got the reply to Scheper-, in full from Medscape, but am unable to find her original essay (s). Do you have a link to what they are replying to? Thanks, Penny T Quote Link to comment Share on other sites More sharing options...
Guest guest Posted August 30, 2007 Report Share Posted August 30, 2007 Hi Penny, I've uploaded the original Scheper- essay into the Files/Transplant info folder (see recent message about a new file upload). The abstract of the article is shown below. I agree with you that it is useful to read her essay before reading the critical comments. She makes some interesting, and sometimes disturbing, observations. Am. J. Transplant. 7: 507-511 (2007) The tyranny of the gift: sacrificial violence in living donor transplants. Scheper- N Organs Watch, 232 Kroeber Hall, University of California-Berkeley, Berkeley, CA, USA. nsh@... Medical anthropology can bring to living donor transplant useful insights on the nature of gifting, family obligations, reciprocity and invisible sacrifice. Whereas, ethical reflections and debates on the marketing of tissues and organs, especially sales by living strangers, have proliferated to the point of saturation, the larger issue of the ethics of " altruistic " donation by and among family members is more rarely the focus of bio-ethical scrutiny and discussion today, though of course it was much debated in the early decades of kidney transplant. As the proportion of living over deceased donors (especially of kidneys) has increased markedly in the past decade, the time is ripe to revisit the topic, which I shall do via three vignettes, all of them informed by my 10 years as founding Director of Organs Watch, an independent, university-based, anthropological and ethnographic field-research and medical human rights project. Whereas living-related (altruistic) and living- unrelated (commercial) donation are often treated as very different phenomena, I will illustrate what social elements are shared. In both instances, paid kidney sellers and related donors, are often responding to family pressures and to a call to " sacrifice " . Comment in: Am J Transplant. 2007 Jul;7(7):1695-7. Am J Transplant. 2007 Mar;7(3):497-8. PMID: 17250554 Best regards, Dave R. > I got the reply to Scheper-, in full from Medscape, but am unable to find her original essay (s). Do you have a link to what they are replying to? Quote Link to comment Share on other sites More sharing options...
Guest guest Posted August 30, 2007 Report Share Posted August 30, 2007 , Thank you very much, you are very clever. Thank you also for all the research and support you give everyone. In the words of my daughter, The article (both actually) has lots of " big words " . Might take a bit of wading through, but I have a free morning, so am looking forward to it. Penny T (in Australia) Ps you can get mangosteen juice and Goji juice here too (down under), but I'm not game to try anything that isn't proven Quote Link to comment Share on other sites More sharing options...
Recommended Posts
Join the conversation
You are posting as a guest. If you have an account, sign in now to post with your account.
Note: Your post will require moderator approval before it will be visible.